WWW.THESIS.DISLIB.INFO
FREE ELECTRONIC LIBRARY - Online materials, documents
 
<< HOME
CONTACTS



Pages:   || 2 |

«W alter Block’s (2003) supposedly “entirely critical” (p. 48) reply greatly narrows the gap between our positions (Caplan 2001, 1999, 1997; ...»

-- [ Page 1 ] --

PROBABILITY AND THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI:

A REPLY TO BLOCK

BRYAN CAPLAN

W alter Block’s (2003) supposedly “entirely critical” (p. 48) reply

greatly narrows the gap between our positions (Caplan 2001,

1999, 1997; Block 1999). It is a major concession for Block to

admit that synthetic a priori propositions can have a low probability and

empirical propositions can have a high probability. The implication, though he does not admit it, is that his initial claims most contrary to common sense are mistaken.

Furthermore, on the general topic of the synthetic a priori, Block incorrectly classifies me as a logical positivist. At no point in my critique did I fault Austrians for their belief in the synthetic a priori, or dismiss any of their positions for failing to be “verifiable” or “falsifiable.” My position is not that their key arguments are methodologically flawed, but that they are mistaken. It may surprise Block, but I fully recognize the existence of synthetic a priori truths.

However, most of his economic examples do not qualify.

Block’s misunderstanding of my methodological position is partially understandable. Though his stereotype does not fit me, it is grounded in fact.

Neoclassical methodologists have long subscribed to some version of logical positivism that working economists routinely flout. But there is no need, I shall argue, for neoclassicals to become praxeologists to eliminate the contradiction. All they need to do is jettison logical positivism and become thoroughgoing Bayesians (Howson and Urbach 1989).

My reply is organized as follows. The second section shows that if synthetic a priori claims, like empirical ones, vary in probability, then Block has no reason to single out the latter as unscientific. Section three sketches my position on the synthetic a priori, and explains the value of empirical testing BRYAN CAPLAN is an associate professor of economics at George Mason University. I would like to thank Peter Boettke, Ed Stringham, Alex Tabarrok, and Tyler Cowen for numerous discussions on these topics, Joseph Salerno for the invitation to respond, and the generous support of the Mercatus Center. The standard disclaimer applies.

THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 6, NO. 3 (FALL 2003): 77–83 78 THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 6, NO. 3 (FALL 2003) of less-than-certain a priori propositions. Section four provides a nonpraxeological solution for the methodological schizophrenia that Block correctly diagnoses in mainstream economics. Section five concludes.

ARE HIGH-PROBABILITY EMPIRICAL CLAIMS “SCIENTIFIC”?

Towards the end of his reply, Block provides the reader with a useful table. Its rows distinguish between empirical and synthetic a priori statements, its columns between low and high probability statements (p. 55; table 2). He then gives examples of all four logical possibilities; for Block, none of the categories are empty. There are high-probability empirical claims, such as “Elephants are very heavy,” and low-probability synthetic a priori claims, like the Pythagorean Theorem. How can synthetic a priori propositions vary in probability? As Block explains: “the more (and more complicated) the steps [in a logical proof], the greater the opportunity for human error”1 (p. 55; table 2).

For example, it is less probable that the minimum wage leads to unemployment than that I now exist. (Table 2 appears in Block’s article in the current issue of this journal.) Block’s table is eminently sensible. Unfortunately, it pulls the rug out from under the methodological position of his earlier reply. In particular, consider the “extreme” claims for which I criticized Block (Caplan 2001, p. 69), such

as:

1. The envious “have no way to prove they lose out at all.” 2. “Scientifically we can know nothing about states of mind not demonstrated in action.” 3. “How can we, as economists, even know they [states of mind not demonstrated in action] exist?” Where do claims about states of mind fit in Block’s typology? At least a fair number must fall into category II—high-probability empirical claims. Take for example “Most socialists would be offended by Defending the Undefendable.” It is hardly true a priori, yet it is plainly true. How then can Block label such a claim scientifically empty? Indeed, how can he call it scientifically inferior to a low-probability synthetic a priori claim? His own typology offers no basis for doing so.

1A corollary, which Block does not explicitly state, is that measures to reduce the opportunity for human error in a proof raise its probability. Even a complex theorem becomes virtually certain if thousands of mathematicians have checked and rechecked it for thousands of years. For this reason, the Pythagorean Theorem is a poor example of a low-probability synthetic a priori claim. For the sake of convenience, however, I will stick with Block’s chosen example.

PROBABILITY AND THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI: A REPLY TO BLOCK 79

One can only guess at the rationale Block would offer. He has already foreclosed one route: equating “scientific knowledge” with certainty. After all, he admits that many synthetic a priori claims—like empirical ones—fall short of certainty. If “Most socialists would be offended by Defending the Undefendable” is unscientific due to lack of certainty, so are claims about the minimum wage.





Might Block instead equate “scientific knowledge” with “synthetic a priori knowledge”? This would be a peculiar position. No one dubs physics and chemistry “unscientific” due to their empirical character. Why should common-sense claims about people’s preferences be held to a higher standard?

To put my point in context: The reason I originally introduced probability was not “as a stick to beat up on the Austrian concept of the synthetic a priori.” (Block 2003, p. 48) My goal, rather, was to use probability as a stick to ward off Austrians’ unwarranted dismissal of common-sense empirical claims about human preferences, indifference, and the like. By admitting that the empirical can be more probable than the synthetic a priori, my critic has distanced himself from the weakest parts of his first reply.

SYNTHETIC A PRIORI A COMMON-SENSE APPROACH TO THE

Many of Block’s examples of the synthetic a priori are poorly chosen. Demand curves, as previously explained, do not necessarily slope downward. Rothbard’s own discussion of backward-bending curves admits as much. Nor is it necessarily true that raising the minimum wage reduces employment, ceteris paribus. It does not have to do so under monopsony.2 Or to take a more fanciful counterexample, imagine that employers have been hypnotized to believe that the minimum wage declines every time Congress increases it. Then raising the minimum wage would increase employment instead of decreasing it, at least until bankruptcy set in.

In spite of these objections, and contrary to my critic’s suspicions, I readily admit that synthetic a priori knowledge exists. I have no complaints about Block’s noneconomic examples (p. 49). My objections to “There are mutual benefits to trade in the ex ante sense,” and “Man acts (to create a world more to his liking in the future than one which would arise but for his action),” are only quibbles. To be strictly true, these assertions would have to allow for indifference: “There are mutual nonlosses to trade in the ex ante sense,” and “Man acts (to create a world as or more to his liking in the future than one which would arise but for his action).” My difference with the Austrians, then, is not on the general question of synthetic a priori knowledge, but on 2Block is incorrect (p. 53, n. 19) to state that I would “demolish the monopsonistic argument” in a graduate class. I think that monopsony is a bona fide exception. This does not mean, of course, that raising the minimum wage always increases the quantity of labor a monopsonist employs, but it can under certain conditions.

80 THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 6, NO. 3 (FALL 2003) the particular question of what qualifies as synthetic a priori. My list is more selective, but it is not blank.

Still, if there are only a handful of bona fide synthetic a priori truths in economics, the relative value of empirical work increases. Moreover, once you admit, as Block does, that synthetic a priori claims vary in probability, then even the synthetic a priori can be empirically tested. Contradictory? Not at all.

It is true, as Austrians have long insisted, that there is no point empirically testing synthetic a priori claims known with certainty. Empirically testing less solid synthetic a priori propositions, in contrast, can be fruitful.

Imagine that we were uncertain about the Pythagorean Theorem. We could spend more time checking the steps of the proof. On the other hand, we might measure a wide variety of triangles to verify that c2=a2+b2. Both efforts would rationally tend to increase our confidence in the theorem, even though neither is foolproof. If we found a clear empirical counterexample, we would conclude that either the premises or the reasoning behind the theorem were incorrect, despite our inability to pinpoint them. Similarly, if we have doubts about Austrian business cycle theory, we might spend years reviewing the steps of the proof, or we might study economic history and look for counterexamples. If less-than-certain empirical evidence contradicts an absolutely certain synthetic a priori claim, then, as the Austrians advise, we should ignore the empirics. The opposite holds if indubitable empirics contradict a less-than-certain synthetic a priori claim.

A BAYESIAN CURE METHODOLOGICAL SCHIZOPHRENIA

FOR

When Block dissects my lecture notes on the minimum wage, he states:

“Would he say it is very likely that this would cause unemployment, or that it is undeniable that it would? I very strongly suspect the latter” (p. 53). He suspects incorrectly. I have already stated that demand curves do not necessarily slope downward, so it would be illogical to proclaim that the disemployment effect of the minimum wage holds without exception. The reason for the unambiguous nature of my lecture notes is precisely the one Block prematurely rejects: They were written for an undergraduate class, where it is hard enough to communicate the main point, let alone any subtleties.

Why then, as Block insightfully asks, do economists react so violently to empirical evidence against the conventional view of the minimum wage’s effect? Why did Block’s dissertation advisor make him run regressions on rent control, then dismiss his anomalous results out of hand? There are three

explanations worth considering:

–  –  –

Explanation #2: Neoclassical economists are intellectually dishonest dogmatists posing as empirical scientists.

Explanation #3: Neoclassical economists are Bayesians with some strong priors.

Explanation #1 is essentially Block’s: Neoclassical economists suffer from methodological schizophrenia. When they shut their eyes and close their ears to contrary empirical evidence on the minimum wage, neoclassicals are doing the epistemically correct thing even though it contradicts their official methodology.

Explanation #2 is routinely offered by economists who publicize their counter-intuitive empirical findings. To some extent, they have a point. There are more than a few economists who claim to be empiricists, but never change their minds about anything—even on questions that Mises himself would have seen as empirical.

For the most part, though, I prefer Explanation #3. The Bayesian model of belief formation permeates neoclassical economics. Since it will be unfamiliar to many Austrians, let me elaborate. The Bayesian model states, in essence, that rational people do not revise their whole worldview every time a new data point emerges. Rather, they marginally update their initial views as facts

comes in—ideally according to Bayes’ Rule, one of the most important formulas in probability theory (Varian 1992, pp. 190–2):

P(B|A)* P(A) P(A|B) = P(B|A)* P(A) + P(B)|not A)* P(not A) P(A) is the “prior probability” of A—the degree of belief you assigned to A before seeing the evidence, B. P(A|B), read “the probability of A given B,” is your “posterior probability”—the degree of belief you assign to A after seeing the evidence, B.3 Now consider the implications of Bayes’ Rule for the Card-Krueger minimum-wage debate. Suppose, based on his pre-Card-Krueger knowledge, that Gary Becker’s P(minimum wage reduces employment) was 98 percent. In Bayesian language, he had a “strong prior”: he was almost, but not quite, sure of the standard conclusion. But recognizing the flaws of empirical research, he might have only weak expectations that any one study would confirm his view. Thus, Becker’s P(Card-Krueger results| minimum wage reduces employment) is, say, 30 percent. Even if he is right about the minimum wage, there is still a 30 percent chance that a careful study by two Princeton economists will find the opposite. Becker would presumably have similar doubts about 3Note that the basis for both the prior probability and the subsequent evidence could be either synthetic a priori or empirical, though admittedly most applications emphasize the latter.

82 THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 6, NO. 3 (FALL 2003) P(Card-Krueger results| minimum wage does not reduce employment). Even if the conventional view were wrong, it is hardly certain that the Card-Krueger empirical test would expose it as such, so Becker assigns this conditional probability a mere 70 percent.

Given all this, what probability should Becker assign to his original view

after reading Card and Krueger’s paper? Using Bayes’ Rule:



Pages:   || 2 |


Similar works:

«ee the one and the multiple An exhibition of artists from Spain and Egypt La Capella, Barcelona : 14 May 2010 – 03 july 2010 Inauguration 14 May 2010 19h30 : Concert by Ehab Abd El Latif Open Night 15 May 2010 19h30 : Screenings and concert by Magdi Mostafa Presentación 18 May 2010 19h30 : Ramon Blecua, Joana Cervia & Pedro Soler Workshop 15 May – 30 May 2010 : Map Embroidery (Vahida Ramujkic, Aviv Kruglanski + participants) The 11 artists of this exhibition have all participated in artist...»

«1 Leave of Absence 04.07.2016 HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES Monday, July 04, 2016 The House met at 1.30 p.m. PRAYERS [MADAM SPEAKER in the Chair] LEAVE OF ABSENCE Madam Speaker: Hon. Members, Dr. Lackram Bodoe MP, Member for Fyzabad, and Miss Marlene Mc Donald MP, Member for Port of Spain South, have requested leave of absence from today’s sitting of the House. Mrs. Christine Newallo-Hosein MP, Member for Cumuto/Manzanilla has requested leave of absence from sittings of the House during the period...»

«Friends & Inclusion Five Approaches to Building Relationships Peggy Hutchison & John Lord with Karen Lord Library and Archives Canada Cataloguing in Publication Hutchison, Peggy, 1950Friends & inclusion : five approaches to building relationships / Peggy Hutchison & John Lord with Karen Lord. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 978-1-895418-95-8 1. Friendship. 2. Social integration. 3. Interpersonal relations.4. People with disabilitiesSocial networks. 5. People with disabilitiesFamily...»

«A report by the Leadership Council of the Sustainable Development Solutions Network Revised working draft for consultation November 25, 2014 16 January 2015 Revised working draft for consultation – 16 January 2015 Revised working draft for consultation – 16 January 2015 About this draft report A first draft of Indicators and a Monitoring Framework for the SDGs was first released by the Sustainable Development Solutions Network (SDSN) in February 2014. It underwent a 1.5 monthlong public...»

«THE GREAT GOD PAN by ARTHUR MACHEN I THE EXPERIMENT I am glad you came, Clarke; very glad indeed. I was not sure you could spare the time. I was able to make arrangements for a few days; things are not very lively just now. But have you no misgivings, Raymond? Is it absolutely safe? The two men were slowly pacing the terrace in front of Dr. Raymond's house. The sun still hung above the western mountain-line, but it shone with a dull red glow that cast no shadows, and all the air was quiet; a...»

«  University of Hertfordshire Hatfield AL10 9AB UK tel +44 (0)1707 284000 fax +44 (0)1707 284115 herts.ac.uk Induction Week 2013 Humanities Dear Student, Congratulations on gaining a place to study in the School of Humanities at the University of Hertfordshire. I would like to welcome you to the University, the School, and to the Humanities Programme, and to draw your attention to a number of key points. Induction Induction week for Humanities students begins on Monday, September 23rd 2013....»

«Case 1:10-cv-23609-JAL Document 1 Entered on FLSD Docket 10/07/2010 Page 1 of 15 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF FLORIDA MIAMI DIVISION CASE NO. SECURITIES AND EXCHANGE COMMISSION, ) ) Plaintiff, ) v. ) ) ANTHONY MELLONE, ) ALEX PARSINIA, ) LARRY WILCOX, ) MACADA HOLDING, INC. f/k/a TRI-STAR HOLDINGS, INC., ) ZCOM NETWORKS, INC., and ) THE UC HUB GROUP, ) ) Defendants. ) ) COMPLAINT Plaintiff Securities and Exchange Commission alleges as follows: I. INTRODUCTION 1. From no...»

«DEVELOPING GUIDELINES FOR A BLUE CARBON TOOLKIT by Avery M. Siciliano Dr. Linwood Pendleton, Advisor May 2015 Masters project submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements fort he Master of Environmental Management degree in the Nicholas School of the Environment of Duke University. i Acknowledgements I would like to thank the project managers and individuals who shared their experiences, thoughts, and insight on blue carbon. It is an exciting time for the field of blue carbon and it is...»

«JOURNAL of DIALOGUE STUDIES Autumn INSTITUTE Volume 3 for DIALOGUE Number 2 STUDIES Editorial Team Academic Editor: Prof Paul Weller Executive Editor: Ozcan Keles Assistant Editors: Mustafa Cakmak, Dr Mustafa Demir, Dr Omer Sener, Frances Sleap, Emma Szewczak-Harris Editorial Board Prof Ronald Arnett Prof Eddie Halpin Prof Ali Paya Duquesne University Leeds Metropolitan University University of Westminster Prof Michael Barnes Dr Carool Kersten Dr Fabio Petito Heythrop College Kings College...»

«Transmission of 20-Gb/s OFDM signals occupying 7-GHz license-free band at 60 GHz using a RoF system employing frequency sextupling optical up-conversion Po-Tsung Shih,1,3 Chun-Ting Lin,2,* Wen-Jr Jiang,1 Han-Sheng Huang,1 Jyehong Chen,1 Anthony Ng’oma,3 Michael Sauer,3 and Sien Chi1,4 Department of Photonics and Institute of Electro-Optical Engineering, National Chiao-Tung University, Hsinchu 300, Taiwan Institute of Photonic System, National Chiao Tung University, Tainan 711, Taiwan. Science...»

«MANAGING CORE RISK IN BANKING Money Laundering & Terrorist Financing Risk Management Guidelines Bangladesh Financial Intelligence Unit BANGLADESH BANK Money Laundering & Terrorist Financing Risk Management Guidelines Bangladesh Financial Intelligence Unit BANGLADESH BANK September, 2015 Editorial Committee Chairman Md. Nasiruzzaman General Manager, Bangladesh Financial Intelligence Unit, Bangladesh Bank Member AKM Ahsan Deputy General Manager, Bangladesh Financial Intelligence Unit, Bangladesh...»

«Violence in the Scriptures: Mormonism and the Cultural Theory of René Girard Mack C. Stirling Introduction Many who revere the scriptures as the inspired word of God are nonetheless disturbed by them. The scriptures contain inconsistencies and outright contradictions. Particularly disturbing for many are scriptural portrayals of God as wrathful, vengeful, and violent. This article will introduce these problems with several examples from the Old Testament, then present a succinct overview of...»





 
<<  HOME   |    CONTACTS
2017 www.thesis.dislib.info - Online materials, documents

Materials of this site are available for review, all rights belong to their respective owners.
If you do not agree with the fact that your material is placed on this site, please, email us, we will within 1-2 business days delete him.